Page:Catholic Encyclopedia, volume 1.djvu/338

This page needs to be proofread.
298

ALEXANDER 298 ALEXANDER Elsewhere decidedly hostile to the Christians as in "Peregrinus Proteus", unquestionably Lucian is in tliis work favourable to them. He shows that while high and low were being led astray by the false mysticism of AlexanikT of Abonoteichos, the Chris- tians lield aloof from him, and with the Epicureans, with whom Lucian markedly contrasts them in the "Peregrinus", shared the full measure of the arch- hypocrite's hate. It is the testimony of an enemy, who here, at least, is no slanderer, but an unwill- ing apologist of Jesus Christ and His persecuted ad- herents. Dr,i. LINGER, Heidcnthum und Judenthum, 644 sqq.; Kell- NER, HrlU'nismua und Chrislenlhum, 89 sq.; H. W. Fowler AND F. O. Fowi.ER. The Works of Lucian rf Samosata (Oxford, 1905), tr. II, 212-23S; Himpel in Kirchenlex., I, 493. John J. a' Becket. Alexander o£ Hales, Franciscan, theologian, and philosopher, one of the greatest of the scholastics, b. at Hales, or Hailles, in Gloucestershire, towards the end of the twelfth century; d. at Paris, in 124.5. He was educated at the monastic school in his native village, and probably also at Oxford. After having finished his studies in England, he went to the University of Paris, and there attained the Jlaster's degree, first in the faculty of arts (philoso- phy), and afterwards in that of theology. From a remark made by Roger Bacon it is inferred that, in 1210, Alexander was Mai/istcr regens in the faculty of arts, and this is the first date of his biography that is certain. Roger is also our authority (though not the only one) that Alexander became arcli- deacon; but whether the title was conferred by the Bishop of Paris or by an English bishop, is uncer- tain. In 1220, Alexander joined the faculty of theology, in which he soon became one of the most celebrated teachers. In 1231, he entered the Order of St. Francis, continuing, however, to perform, as a monk, the duties of a licensed teacher of theology, a fact which was of the utmost importance both for the University and for the course of studies in the Franciscan Order. Alexander died at the convent of his Order in Paris. In the chronicles and theological treatises of the fourteenth century we find Alexander styled Doctor irreJTagabUvi, Fans Vita;, Theologorum monarcha. His principal work is the " Summa Universse Tlieologia"", begun about the year 12.31 and left unfinished. The third part is defective, especially the portion treat- ing of the virtues and other questions in moral tlieology. To supply this defect, the "Summa Virtutum " was com|30sed by the Franciscan William of Melitona, though the work was, and is still some- times, ascribed to Alexander himself. It is now agreed that not Alexander of Hales, but Alexander of Bonini is the author of the "Commentaries" on Aristotle's "Metaphysics" and "De Anima." The "Summa Theologia;" has been several times pub- lished (Venice, 1475, l.-iTfi; Nuremberg, 14S1, 1502; Pavia, 14.S1; Cologne, 1622). A critical edition has recently been promised by the Quaracchi editors of the works of St. Bonaventure. Alexander's other works (Salimbene, a contemporary, speaks of his "many writings") arc still unpublished. Alexander's importance for the history of theology and philosophy lies in the fact, that he was tlic first to attempt a .systematic exposition of Catholic doctrine, after the metaphysical and physical works of Aristotle had become known to the schoolmen. His is not the first "Summa". The collections of ".Sentences", which were current in the schools since the days of Abelard, were summaries of theology, and were often so titled in manuscripts. .So that Alexander had many Summists as predecessors for instance: Hugh of St. Victor, Roland, Omnebene, I'ctcr Lombard, Stephen Langton, Robert of Mehm, Peter of Poitiers, William of Au.xerre, and Robert Pulleyn. His, however, is the first "Summa" in which use was made of Aristotle's physical, meta- physical, and ethical, as well as logical treatises. Peter Lombard did not quote Aristotle once; Alex- ander quotes him in almost every Qucestio; he quotes also Arabian commentators, especially Avicenna, and thus prepares the way for Albert, St. Thomas, St. Bonaventure, and Duns Scotus for whom Aris- totle was the philosopher. The "Summa" is divided into four parts: the first treats of God, the Trinity, etc.; the second, of creatures, sin, etc.; the third, of Christ, Redemption, supernatural law; the fourth, of the sacraments. Each Part is divided into Ques- tions, each Question into Members, each Member into Articles. The method is a development of that employed by Abelard in his "Yea and Nay", and is practically that with which readers of St. Thomas are familiar. The article opens with a recital of the objections, then follows the thesis, with proofs, scriptural, patristic, and rational, and at the end of the article, under the title Resolutio are given the answers to the objections. Alexander's theology is, in its main outline.s, identical with that of St. Bonaventure and St. Thomas. Thus he starts with the question of the knowableness of God, and decides that, while the human mind can know that He is, no created mind can comprehend what He is. In enumerating the proofs of the existence of God, he lays stress on St. Augustine's argument from the need of an abso- lute truth, on St. Anselm's ontological argument, on Hugh of St. Victor's argument from conscious- ness, and on the Aristotelean argument from causality. He teaches that God is the exemplar, efficient and final cause of all things, that He is the Creator and Preserver of all things, that He is pure Actuality (Actus Purus). all tilings else being composed of matter and form. This latter point, the coexten- siveness of matter with created being, later on became a distinctive tenet of the Franciscan School. On the problem of Universals, Alexander takes up the position of a metaphysician and psychologist, and thus reaches a conclusion to which his predecessors of the twelfth century, who argued the question solely from the point of view of dialectics, could never have attained; he teaches that L^niversals exist ante rem, in the mind of God, and also in re, as forms or es- sences which the active intellect abstracts. This is the conclusion of Moderate Realism. In psychology, more than elsewhere, Alexander shows that he is not prepared to break with the traditional Augustinian teadiing which prevailed in the schools before the introduction of Aristotle's "De Anima". Thus he adopts the threefold division of the faculties of the soul into ratio, which has for its object the external world, intcUrctus, which has for its object created spiritual substances, and intcHigcntia, which has for its object first principles and the eternal prototypes of things in the mind of God. Augustinian, also, is the doctrine that our knowledge of higher truths, especially of higher spiritual truths, is dependent on special divine illumination. Despite these Augustinian principles, however, he adopts Aristotle's doctrine of the Active and Passive In- tellect, and by means of it accounts for our knowledge of the external world. Alexander's importance m the history of Christian Etliics is due to the use which he makes of Aristotle's ethical treatises. William of Auxerre, in his "Summa Aurea", made use of a Latin tran.slation of Aristotle's "Ethics"; following his example, though working along indeiicndent lines, Alexander takes up the problems of the Highest Good, the nature of virtue, the moral aspects of ac- tions and habits, and brings to bear on his discus- sions not merely the principles of the evangelical law, the ethical definitions of patristic writers, the legislation and practice of the Church, but also the