Page:Catholic Encyclopedia, volume 5.djvu/637

This page needs to be proofread.

ETHICS


565


ETHICS


monarchy; the aristocracy; the democracy. The monarchy is hereditary or elective, according as suc- cession to supreme power follows the right of primo- geniture of a family (djTiasty) or is subject to suf- frage. At the present day the only existing kind of monarchy is the liereditary, the elective monarchies, such as Poland and the old German Sovereigntj', having long since disappeared. Those States in which the sovereign power resides in the body of the people, are called polycracies, or more commonly, republics, and are divided into aristocracies and democracies. In republics the sovereigntj' is vested in the people. The latter elect from their number representatives who frame their laws and administer the affairs of govern- ment in their name. The almost imiversally prevailing form of government in Europe, fashioned upon the model created by England, is the constitutional mon- archy, a mixture of the monarchical, aristocratic, and democratic forms. The law-making power is vested in the king and two chambers. The members of one chamber represent the aristocratic and conservative element, while the other chamber, elected from the body of citizens, represents the democratic element. The monarch himself is responsible to no one, yet his governmental acts require the counter-signature of the ministers, who in turn are responsible to the chamber.

With regard to its appointed functions the govern- ment of the State is divided into the legislative, judi- ciary, and executive powers. It is of primary impor- tance that the State enact general and stable laws governing the activities of its subjects, as far as this is required for the good order and well-bemg of the whole body. For this purpose it must possess the right to legislate; it must, moreover, carry out these laws and provide, by means of the administrative, or rather executive, power for what is needful to the general good of the community; finally, it has to punish in- fractions of the laws and authoritatively settle legal disputes, and for this purpose it has need of the judi- ciary power (in civil and criminal courts). This right of the State to impose penalties is founded on the necessity of preserving good order and of providing for the security of the whole body politic. In a com- munity there are always found those who can in no other way be effectually forced to observe the laws and respect the rights of others than by the infliction of punishment. Hence the State mvist have the right to enact penal statutes, calculated to deter its subjects from violating the laws, and the right, moreover, to actually inflict punishment after the violation has occurred. Among the legitimate modes of pimish- ment is capital punishment. It is considered, and rightly so, a step forward in civilization, that nowa- days a milder practice has been adopted in this regard, and that capital pimishment is more rarely inflicted, and then only for such heinous crimes as murder and high treason. Nevertheless, humanitarian sentimen- tal ism has no doubt been carried to an exaggerated degree, so much so that many would on principle do away with capital punishment altogether. And yet, this is the only sanction sufficiently effective to deter some men from committing the gravest crimes.

When it is asserted, with Aristotle, that the State is a society sufficient for itself, this is to be considered true in the sense that the State needs no further devel- opment to complete its organization, but not in the sense that it is independent in every respect. The greater the advance of mankind in progress and civili- zation, the more necessary and frequent the commu- nication between nations becomes. Hence the ques- tion arises as to what rights and duties mutually exist between nation and nation. That portion of ethics which treats this question from a philosophical stand- point is called the theory of international law, or of the law of nations. Of course, many writers of the present day deny the propriety of a philosophical


treatment of international law. According to them the only international rights and duties are those which have been established by some positive measure either implicitly or explicitly agreed upon. This, in- deed, is the position that must be taken by all who reject the natural law. On the other hand, this posi- tion precludes the possibility of any positive inter- national law whatever, for lasting and binding com- pacts between various States are possible only when the primarj- principle of right is recognized — that it is just and obligatory to stand by lawful agreements. Now this is a principle of natural law; hence, those who deny the existence of the natvual law (e. g. E. von Hartmann) must consequently reject any interna- tional law properly so called. In their opinion inter- national agreements are mere conventions, which each one observes as long as he finds it necessary or advan- tageous. And so we are eventually led back to the principles of ancient paganism, which, in the inter- course between nations, too often identified right with might. But Christianity brought the nations into a closer union and broke down the barriers of narrow- minded policy. It proclaimed, moreover, the duties of love and just ice as binding on all nations, thus restoring and perfecting the natural law. The fimdamental principles: "Give each one his due", "Do injury to no man", " Do not to others what you would not have them do to you", etc., have an absolute and imiversal value, and hence must obtain also in the intercourse between nations. Purely natural duties and rights are common to all nations; the acquired or positive ones may vary considerably. Various, too, are the rights and duties of nations in peace and in war. Since, however, there are, under this head, many details of a doubtful and changeable character, the codification of international law is a most urgent desideratum. Be- sides this an international court should be established to attend to the execution of the various measures promulgated bj' the law and to arbitrate in case of dispute. The foimdations of such an international court of arbitration have been laid at The Hague; un- fortunately, its competence has been hitherto very much restricted, and besides, it exercises its functions only when the Powers at variance appeal to it of their own accord. In the codification of international law no one would be more competent to lend effective co- operation and to maintain the principles of justice and love which should exist between nations in their inter- course with one another, than the pope. No one can offer sounder guarantees for the righteousness of the principles to be laid down, and no one can exert greater moral influence towards carrying them into effect. This is even recognized by unprejudiced Protestants. At the Vatican Council not only the many Catholic bishops present, but the Protestant David Urquhart appealed to the pope to draw up a schedule of the more important principles of interna- tional law, which were to be binding on all Christian nations. Religious prejudice, however, places many difficulties in the way of realizing this plan.

Meyer. TnstitiUiones juris n/ituralis scu philosophic moralis UTii'iiTs,! (Freiburg. 2ded., 1906,). I; (1900\ II; Schiffixi. Dis- pulntione.-. philosophic moralis (Turin. 1891). II: Costa-Ros- SE-rrr, Phitosophia moralis (Innsbruck, 2d ed., 18S6): Frins, Dc actibus humanis (Freiburg. 2 vols., 1897-1904): Ferretti, Institutiones pkiloso^hus moralis (Rome, 3 vols., 1st ed., 188.5); Castelein, Institutiones philosophic moralis et socialis (Brus- sels. 1899); Id., Droit nalurd (Paris. 1903): Gutberlet, Elhih und .Valurrecht (Munsler, 3d ed.. 1901); de Pascal. Philosophic morale et soeiale (Paris, ISgt-g.l): Zigliara, Summa phUoso- phica: III, Philosophia moralis (Lyons, 3d ed., 1880); Libera- tore, Institutiones ethiett et juris naturalis (Prate, 7th ed., 1880): Austin. The Duties and Kinhts of Afan (London, 2d ed., 1888); MiNO, The Data of Modern Ethics Examined (New York, 2d ed., 1S97): Russo. De philosophiA mnrali prcelectiones (1891); .InsEPn RicKABY. Aforal Philosophy (London. 1888); Stockl, Lehrhueh der Philosophie: III. Elhitc, Social- und R eehlsphiloio- phie (Mainz, 7th ed., 1892); Lehmen, Lehrbuch der Philosophie: IV, Moralphnosophie (Freiburg, 1906); Willems, Philosophia moralis (Trier. 1908); Rosmini, Sloria comparativa e critica dei sistemi intomo al principio delta morale (Milan, 1837); Weksek, Grundriaa exner Geschichle der Moralphiloaophie