Page:Encyclopædia Britannica, Ninth Edition, v. 5.djvu/158

This page needs to be proofread.
146
CARTESIANISM
[des cartes.

" contains in Irimself formatter all tliat is in mind, but only eminenter all that is in matter;"[1] or, as he elsewhere expresses it more popularly, he is mind, but he is only the creator of matter. And for this he gives as his reason, that matter as being divisible and passive is essentially imperfect. ] psa natura corporis multas imperfectiones involvit, and, therefore, " there is more analogy between sounds and colours than there is between material things and God." But the real imperfection here lies in the abstractness of the Cartesian conception of matter as merely extended, merely passive; and this is balanced by the equal abstractness of the conception of mind or self -consciousness as an absolutely simple activity, a pure intelligence without any object but itself. If matter as absolutely opposed to mind is imperfect, mind as absolutely opposed to matter is equally imperfect. In fact they are the elements or factors of a unity, and lose all meaning when .severed from each other, and if we are to seek this unity by abstraction, we must equally abstract

from both.

The result of this one-sidedness is seen in the fact that Des Cartes, who begins by separating mind from matter, cuds by finding the essence of mind in pure will, i.e., in pure formal self-determination. Hence God s will is conceived as absolutely arbitrary, not determined by any end or law, f or all laws, even the necessary truths that constitute reason," spring from God s determination, and do not precede it. " He is the author of the essence of things no less than their existence," and his will has no reason but his will. In man there is an intelligence with eternal laws or truths involved in its structure, which so far limits his will. " He finds the nature of good and truth already determined by God, and his will cannot be moved by anything else." His highest freedom consists in having his will determined by a clear perception of the nature of good and truth, and " he is never indifferent except when he is ignorant of it, or at least does not see it so clearly as to be lifted above the possibility of doubt."[2] Indifference of will is to him " the lowest grade of liberty," yet, on the other hand, in nothing does the image of God in him show itself more clearly than in the fact that his will is not limited by his clear and distinct knowledge, but is " in a manner infinite." For "there is no object; of any will, even the infinite will of God, to which our will does not extend."[3] Belief is a free act, for as we can yield our assent to the obscure conceptions presented by sense and the imagina tion, and thus allow ourselves to be led into error, so on the other hand we can refuse to give this assent, or allow ourselves to be determined by anything but the clear and distinct ideas of intelligence. That which makes it possible for us to err is that also in which the divine image in us is most clearly seen. We cannot have the freedom of God whose will creates the object of his knowledge ; but in reserving our assent for the clear and distinct perceptions of intelligence, we, as it were, re-enact for ourselves the divine law, and repeat, so far as is possible to finite beings, the transcendent act of will in which truth and good had their origin.

The inherent defect of this view is the divorce it makes between the form and the matter of intelligence. It implies that reason or self-consciousness is one thing, and that truth is another and quite different thing, which has been united to it by the arbitrary will of God. The same external conception of the relation of truth to the mind is involved in the doctrine of innate ideas. It is true that Des Cartes did not hold that doctrine in the coarse form in which it was attributed to him by Locke, but expressly declares that he has " never said or thought at any time that the mind required innate ideas which were separated from the faculty of thinking. He had simply used the word innate to distinguish those ideas which are derived from that faculty, and not from external objects or the determination of the will. Just as when we say generosity is innate in certain families, and in certain others diseases, like the gout or the stone, we do not mean to imply that infants in their mother s womb are affected with these complaints."[4] Yet Des Cartes, as we have seen, does not hold that these truths are involved in the very nature of intelligence as such, so that we cannot conceive a self-con scious being without them. On the contrary we are to regard the divine intelligence as by arbitrary act determining that two and two should be four, or that envy should be a vice. We are " not to conceive eternal truth flowing from God as rays from the sun."[5] In other words, we are not to conceive all particular truths as different aspects of one truth. It is part of the imperfection of man s finite nature that he " finds truth and good determined for him." It is something given, given, indeed, along with his very faculty of thinking, but still given as an external limit to it. It belongs not to his nature as spirit, but to his finitude as man.

After what has been said, it is obvious that the transition

from God to matter must be somewhat arbitrary and external. God s truthfulness is pledged for the reality of that of which we have clear and distinct ideas ; and we have clear and distinct ideas of the external world so long as we conceive it simply as extended matter, infinitely divisible, and moved entirely from without, so long, in short, as we conceive it as the direct opposite of mind, and do not attribute to it any one of the properties of mind. Omnes proprietates, quas in ea dare percipinms, ad hoc unum reducuntiir, quod sit jmrlibilis et mobili-s, secundum partes. We must, therefore, free ourselves from the obscure and confused modes of thought which arise whenever we attribute any of the secondary qualities, which exist merely in our sensations, to the objects that cause these sensations. The subjective character of such qualities is proved by the constant change which takes place in them, without any change of the object in which they are perceived. A piece of wax cannot lose its extension ; but its colour, its hard ness, and all the other qualities whereby it is presented to sense, may be easily altered. What is objective in all this is merely an extended substance, and the modes of motion or rest through which it is made to pass. In like manner we must separate from our notion of matter all ideas of actio in distans, e.g., we must explain weight not as a tendency to the centre of the earth or an attraction of distant particles of matter, but as a consequence of the pressure of other bodies, immediately surrounding that which is felt to be heavy.[6] For the only conceivable actio in distans is that which is mediated by thought, and it is only in so far as we suppose matter to have in it a principle of activity like thought, that we can accept such explana tions of its motion. Again, while we must thus keep our conception of matter clear of all elements that do not belong to it, we must also be careful not to take away from it those that do belong to it. It is a defect of distinctness in our ideas when we conceive an attribute as existing apart from its substance, or a substance without its attribute; for this is to treat elements that are only separated by a " distinction of reason," as if they were dis tinct things. The conception of the possibility of a vacuum or empty space-arises merely from our confusing the possible separation of any mode or form of matter from matter in

general with the impossible separation of matter in general

  1. ftesp. ad sec. object., p. 72-3.
  2. Resp. Sexto:, 160-163.
  3. Principia, i. 35.
  4. KotoR in Programma, p. 184.
  5. Epistoloe, i. 110,
  6. Resp. Sextuc, p. 165-6