There was a problem when proofreading this page.

this paper, the central question is whether ChatGPT has intentions and or beliefs. Does it intend to deceive? Can it, in any literal sense, be said to have goals or aims? If so, does it intend to deceive us about the content of its utterances, or merely have the goal to appear to be a competent speaker? Does it have beliefs—internal representational states which aim to track the truth? If so, do its utterances match those beliefs (in which case its false statements might be something like hallucinations) or are its utterances not matched to the beliefs—in which case they are likely to be either lies or bullshit? We will consider these questions in more depth in Sect. 3.2.2.

There are other philosophically important aspects of agenthood that we will not be considering. We won’t be considering whether ChatGPT makes decisions, has or lacks autonomy, or is conscious; we also won’t worry whether ChatGPT is morally responsible for its statements or its actions (if it has any of those).

ChatGPT is a bullshit machine

We will argue that even if ChatGPT is not, itself, a hard bullshitter, it is nonetheless a bullshit machine. The bullshitter is the person using it, since they (i) don’t care about the truth of what it says, (ii) want the reader to believe what the application outputs. On Frankfurt’s view, bullshit is bullshit even if uttered with no intent to bullshit: if something is bullshit to start with, then its repetition “is bullshit as he [or it] repeats it, insofar as it was originated by someone who was unconcerned with whether what he was saying is true or false” (2022, p340).

This just pushes the question back to who the originator is, though: take the (increasingly frequent) example of the student essay created by ChatGPT. If the student cared about accuracy and truth, they would not use a program that infamously makes up sources whole-cloth. Equally, though, if they give it a prompt to produce an essay on philosophy of science and it produces a recipe for Bakewell tarts, then it won’t have the desired effect. So the idea of ChatGPT as a bullshit machine seems right, but also as if it’s missing something: someone can produce bullshit using their voice, a pen or a word processor, after all, but we don’t standardly think of these things as being bullshit machines, or of outputting bullshit in any particularly interesting way – conversely, there does seem to be something particular to ChatGPT, to do with the way that it operates, which makes it more than a mere tool, and which suggests that it might appropriately be thought of as an originator of bullshit. In short, it doesn’t seem quite right either to think of ChatGPT as analogous to a pen (can be used for bullshit, but can create nothing without deliberate and wholly agent-directed action) nor as to a bullshitting human (who can intend and produce bullshit on their own initiative).

The idea of ChatGPT as a bullshit machine is a helpful one when combined with the distinction between hard and soft bullshit. Reaching again for the example of the dodgy student paper: we’ve all, I take it, marked papers where it was obvious that a dictionary or thesaurus had been deployed with a crushing lack of subtlety; where fifty-dollar words are used not because they’re the best choice, nor even because they serve to obfuscate the truth, but simply because the author wants to convey an impression of understanding and sophistication. It would be inappropriate to call the dictionary a bullshit artist in this case; but it would not be inappropriate to call the result bullshit. So perhaps we should, strictly, say not that ChatGPT is bullshit but that it outputs bullshit in a way that goes beyond being simply a vector of bullshit: it does not and cannot care about the truth of its output, and the person using it does so not to convey truth or falsehood but rather to convince the hearer that the text was written by a interested and attentive agent.

ChatGPT may be a hard bullshitter

Is ChatGPT itself a hard bullshitter? If so, it must have intentions or goals: it must intend to deceive its listener, not about the content of its statements, but instead about its agenda. Recall that hard bullshitters, like the unprepared student or the incompetent politician, don’t care whether their statements are true or false, but do intend to deceive their audience about what they are doing. If so, it must have intentions or goals: it must intend to deceive its listener, not about the content of its statements, but instead about its agenda. We don’t think that ChatGPT is an agent or has intentions in precisely the same way that humans do (see Levenstein and Herrmann (forthcoming) for a discussion of the issues here). But when speaking loosely it is remarkably easy to use intentional language to describe it: what is ChatGPT trying to do? Does it care whether the text it produces is accurate? We will argue that there is a robust, although perhaps not literal, sense in which ChatGPT does intend to deceive us about its agenda: its goal is not to convince us of the content of its utterances, but instead to portray itself as a ‘normal’ interlocutor like ourselves. By contrast, there is no similarly strong sense in which ChatGPT confabulates, lies, or hallucinates.

Our case will be simple: ChatGPT’s primary function is to imitate human speech. If this function is intentional, it is precisely the sort of intention that is required for an agent to be a hard bullshitter: in performing the function, ChatGPT is attempting to deceive the audience about its agenda. Specifically, it’s trying to seem like something that has an agenda, when in many cases it does not. We’ll discuss here