also presented as absolutely valid for the content of
that principle. Again: if there should be, besides
this absolute first principle, still other fundamental
principles of the science of knowledge—which in
that case can only be partly absolute, and must be
partly derived from the first principle, since otherwise
in the first case they would not be fundamental
principles, and in the latter case not connected
with the first and highest principle—then the absolute part of these other fundamental principles could
only be either the content or the form; and, likewise, the conditioned or derived part of these principles could only be either the content or the form.
If the content of these other fundamental principles
be their absolute or unconditioned part, then the
absolute first principle of the science of knowledge
must condition the form of those contents; or if
the form of those other principles be the unconditioned
part, then their content must be conditioned
by the first principle of the science of knowledge;
and thus indirectly also their form, that is, in so far
as the form is to be form of the content. In either
case, therefore, the form would be determined by
the first absolute principle of the science of knowledge.
And since it is impossible that there should
be a fundamental principle not determined either in
form or in content by the first absolute principle,
(that is, if we are to have a science of knowledge at
all,) it follows that there can only be three fundamental
principles: one absolutely in and through
itself determined both in form and in content; a
Page:Fichte Science of Knowledge.djvu/66
24
INTRODUCTION