Page:Mary Whiton Calkins - Review of Manaism - A Study in the Psychology of Religion (The Harvard Theological Review, 1919-01-01).pdf/1

This page has been proofread, but needs to be validated.
Book Reviews
459

Manaism: A Study in the Psychology of Religion. Ivy G. Campbell. (American Journal of Psychology, January, 1918). Pp. 49.

Students of either the psychology or the history of religion should not overlook Professor I. G. Campbell’s study of manaism. By manaism Dr. Campbell means the preanimistic theory “that man first explains things, not in analogy to his own soul, as animism holds, but rather by postulating a great force” (p. 2). This force is known as mana, Wakanda, or orenda. The author bases her analysis of manaism on a painstaking examination of field workers’ reports. The following quotation indicates the extent of Dr. Campbell’s sources: “Not only the beliefs of primitive people quoted by the holders of this theory [manaism] but also comparable ones from other parts of the world have been considered. … In presenting the compilation of material gathered from reports of primitive peoples, selection has been made of that gathered from parts of the world which have not previously found a large place in the literature of preanimistic discussions. Since the data from North America and Australia have been previously extensively cited, this study, in order to uphold its contentions, stresses the data of Africa and Australasia, exclusive of Australia” (p. 2).

From her study of this material Dr. Campbell reaches the significant conclusion that primitive people do not, as a matter of fact, regard mana as impersonal. The conventional view that mana means impersonal force is attributed by Dr. Campbell to a confusion of three uses of the word “impersonal.” The term, she truly says, “has been used in one of three ways, as equivalent to (1) mechanical, (2) non-bodily, (3) super-individual” (p. 17). She admits that mana is impersonal in the second and third of these senses—that it does not belong to one concrete individual human body and that it is a super-individual or collective power. But she contends that mana may be both incorporeal and over-individual without being impersonal or mechanical in the first, the literal sense of the term. The conception of mana as literally impersonal, though held by Leuba, Schmidt, and others (p. 17) is, in Miss Campbell’s opinion, flatly opposed to the testimony of “nearly all the field-workers,” for they “report mana as spiritual.” She herself conceives of mana as personal power experienced by man “when he is acting with his group” (p. 353)—a power which he may “eject” into a higher being, and even into a God (p. 422 et al). In the following comparison with Durkheim’s theory she accentuates the significant features of her own: “Both,” she says, “make the contrast of the social and the individual self the basis on which religion is built up; but whereas he makes everything connected