Page:Russell, Whitehead - Principia Mathematica, vol. I, 1910.djvu/150

This page has been proofread, but needs to be validated.
*5. Miscellaneous Propositions.

Summary of *5.

The present number consists chiefly of propositions of two sorts: (1) those which will be required as lemmas in one or more subsequent proofs, (2) those which are on their own account illustrative, or would be important in other developments than those that we wish to make. A few of the propositions of this number, however, will be used very frequently. These are:

*5·1.

I.e. two propositions are equivalent if they are both true. (The statement that two propositions are equivalent if they are both false is *5·21.)

*5·32.

I.e. to say that, on the hypothesis , and are equivalent, is equivalent to saying that the joint assertion of and is equivalent to the joint assertion of and . This is a very useful rule in inference.

*5·6.

I.e. " and not- imply " is equivalent to " implies or ."

Among propositions never subsequently referred to, but inserted for their intrinsic interest, are the following: *5·11·12·13·14, which state that, given any two propositions , , either or must imply , and must imply either or not-, and either implies or implies ; and given any third proposition , either implies or implies [1].

Other propositions not subsequently referred to are *5·22·23·24; in these it is shown that two propositions are not equivalent when, and only when, one is true and the other false, and that two propositions are equivalent when, and only when, both are true or both false. It follows (*5·24) that the negation of "" is equivalent to "." *5·54·55 state that both the product and the sum of and are equivalent, respectively, either to or to .

The proofs of the following propositions are all easy, and we shall therefore often merely indicate the propositions used in the proofs.


  1. Cf. Schröder, Vorlesungen über Algebra der Logik, Zweiter Band (Leipzig, 1891), pp. 270–271, where the apparent oddity of the above proposition is explained.